Pushing backward beyond the penal substitution atonement theory we reach back all the way to Anselm, Archbishop of Canterbury (1033 – 1109). In 1098 he published his views on the atonement in Cur Deus Homo (Why Did God Become Human?) in which he proposed what became known as the satisfaction atonement theory. Anselm felt that the commonly accepted christus victor theory which had been around for a thousand years of Christian history no longer communicated the gospel clearly to his contemporaries. He also felt it granted too much power and authority to the Devil.
The satisfaction atonement theory can best be understood when seen in light of the historical context in which it emerged. The dominant social structure of the time was the feudal system; a carefully managed series of reciprocal obligations. Lords living in castles offered protection to villagers (vassals) and kept the community in order by maintaining justice and the rights of the people. In return, vassals honored their lords by paying homage in words, deeds and the payment of money or goods. On the religious scene, it was a time in which penance was practiced as a way of obtaining forgiveness for sins committed.
Although Anselm may not have been conscious of it, he framed his theological beliefs about atonement according to the worldview of his culture and contemporary church experience. So the hypotheses of the satisfaction atonement theory are quite predictable: God, the Lord, provided a perfectly balanced world for humans to inhabit. Yet, by disobeying God, humans offended his honor and sent the universe spinning out of kilter. In order to escape punishment in hell, humans must “satisfy” the debt due God’s offended honor which will allow God to restore order to the universe. However the problem is that an offense against an infinite God can never be paid by a finite person; it had to be paid by another infinite person – which would need to be God himself. That is why God sent the God-man, Jesus, to suffer and die in order to provide satisfaction to God and restore his honor, although Anselm insisted that the divine part of Jesus was spared the suffering. What makes this theory operative is that this “excess penance” is then transferred to all who believe this narrative and the need for punishment is eliminated. Fait accompli!
There are some positive things to be said about this theory. Anselm succeeded in explaining to his contemporaries what Jesus accomplished on the cross using images easily intelligible to them. Furthermore, his theory deals with sin in an objective way and on a cosmic level by offering a psychologically plausible way of confronting the problem; it appeals to common human perceptions of right and wrong, guilt and innocence, and punishment and pardon. And, unlike in the penal substitutionary theory, Anselm does not present a wrathful God intent on punishing sin, but focuses on Christ willingly satisfying or paying the debt we owe.
But there are some significant weaknesses in the satisfaction atonement theory as well. One of the most significant is that it forms the basis for the penal substitutionary theory that emerged in later centuries. While it can be argued that Anselm’s theory portrays God in a more positive light, it was not a big step to move from the Lord whose honor was offended to a stern Judge intent on punishing sin. But there are other problems with the satisfaction atonement theory itself:
More than a millennium after Jesus death, Anselm’s satisfaction atonement theory opened the door to a second millennium dominated by thoughts of divine punishment for human sin as the only way to avoid eternal damnation in hell. So our search for more satisfactory atonement rhetoric continues.